The Constitution of the Legal Responsibility of Institutional Discrimination

来源 :Frontiers of Legal Research | 被引量 : 0次 | 上传用户:knightxmu
下载到本地 , 更方便阅读
声明 : 本文档内容版权归属内容提供方 , 如果您对本文有版权争议 , 可与客服联系进行内容授权或下架
论文部分内容阅读
  Abstract
  As a kind of typical public law discrimination, institutional discrimination brings violation to the citizens’ equal rights. Therefore, discrimination body’s legal liability shall be pursued. All in all, the legal responsibility of institutional discrimination is a public law responsibility which is made up of the public power as main infringement subject, formal and informal regulations as infringement action, and the coexist of fault and innocence as subjective status.
  Key words: Institutional discrimination; Infringement subject; Infringement action; Subjective status
  Zhou, L. J. (2015). The Constitution of the Legal Responsibility of Institutional Discrimination. Frontiers of Legal Research, 3(1), -0. Available from http://www.cscanada.net/index.php/flr/article/view/10.3968/5414 DOI: 10.3968/5414
  INTRODUTION
  Institutional discrimination is because that the formal acknowledgement of the state or the execution of public power causes certain amount of social groups continuously suffering common and standard unreasonable treatment. As a kind of typical public law discrimination, institutional discrimination brings violation to certain social groups’ equal rights. Since public power subject diverged from the distribution of justice in the process of designing the institution, then we should investigate its legal responsibility to amend the already violated civil rights.
  1. PUBLIC POWER SUBJECT
  From the concept of institutional discrimination it is not difficult for us to get the point that the infringement subject of institutional discrimination is public power subject. The research focus of modern public law gradually turns to the performance of public functions. That is to say,
  on one hand, public law positively deals with public functional departments’ functions, structures, organizations, and procedures; on the other hand, by setting up and perform public functional departments’ responsibilities to negatively mange, control, and supervise the performance of public functions. (Cane, 2008)
  It has broadened the research field of public law in a large degree. However, at the same time, the expansion of public law research has made the public power subject’s scope a bit vague. After all, whether a function is public or not is a normative not a factual question. When vague public power subject meets indistinct institutional discrimination, the problem seems to get more complicated.   This paper thinks that within the research framework of institutional discrimination, we can at least divide institutional discrimination infringement subject into legislative organs, administrative organs, judicial organs, and other public power subjects. As provided by the Constitution, legislative organs, administrative organs, and judicial organs are most formal legal institutions’ designers and promoters. In the process of the design and promotion of legal institutions, even judicial organs which are thought as the guardians of the Constitution have the possibility to violate citizens’ equal rights or get involved in institutional discrimination, not to say that legislative organs can vacillate among different discriminations based on different parties’ or regions’ disputes on interests or administrative organs diverge away from the goal of public interest to realize officials’ or interest groups’ self-interests by violating citizens’ equal rights. Such phenomenon is especially obvious in China. Since the Supreme People’s Court has judicial interpretation power, thus, judicial organs do have institutional discrimination upon citizens in certain circumstances in practice. For example, according to the stipulation of “The Supreme Court’s Judicial Interpretation and Law-Application for Personal Injury Cases”: “Compensation for death shall be 20 times of the per capita disposable annual income or rural per capita net income of the court of claim”, such judicial interpretation has caused the institutional tragedy that urban and rural residents’ lives are of “different prices”. (Ren, 2007) As to the other public power subjects, this article makes reference to Prof. LI, Haiping’s idea to call them as non-state public power or social public power. According to the understanding of Prof. Li, non-state public power is “enjoyed by the organizations that do not stipulate in the Constitution as state organs.” (Li, 2012, November 24) The scope of non-state power at least contains political parties, People’s organizations, and social organizations. The common place of these organizations is that they all have public affair management power in certain forms or in different degrees and therefore can make discriminatory institutional arrangement on their members or other citizens in certain scope.
  In fact, non-state public power does not only exist in China, it can be found in many countries and regions around the world. And the institutional discriminations made by non-state public power subjects are not rare of ordinary occurrence. For example, in the “Smith vs. Alwright, 321 US. 650” case in 1944 USA, democratic Convention of the State of Texas passed a resolution that colored races are banned from being democrats or attending elections of the Congressmen, state governors, or other officials (Zhang, 2004). Apparently, such resolution of Texas Democratic Party is a kind of institutional discrimination on the election rights of colored races within the scope of Texas, therefore, it was finally aborted by the Federal Supreme Court. As we can see that even in countries like the USA which have well developed political and legal systems, institutional discrimination is inevitable. It is not very difficult for us to imagine that   in countries with less developed political and legal systems, policies made by political parties can become documents with legal force in practice to bind governmental organizations. Under this circumstance, the state organs carrying out such policies made by the political parties, it is possible for them to violate citizens’ basic rights. (Yao, 2006)
  2. THE FORMAL AND INFORMAL SYSTEMS
  Since institutional discrimination is carried out by public power subjects through institutional design, then the design and implementation of the systems are apparently the infringement act of institutional discrimination. According to different ways of the setups of the systems, there are formal and informal systems. The former one is “a series of regulations or rules created by organization members, especially the leading groups, on purpose on the basis of social life experience.” (Si, 2011) The latter on refers to “a series of restrictions recognized by the society and gradually formed during people’s long term social interactions.” (Wang, 2005). Although informal system is mainly shown as traditional concepts, moral standards, village regulations and agreements, customs, and ideologies and so on, and is “basically implemented under the non-mandatory force or ‘soft constraining’ such as public opinion and self-restriction of social members” (Xin, 2005), this does not rule out the important role played by state power on the formation of informal systems. Xiebosier and Weigast explicitly pointed out in a research about the institutional foundation of committees’ power that
  those congressional committees powers which cannot be explained by formal regulations, are formed from a set of informal and unwritten restrictions and those restrictions evolved under the background of participants’ repeated interactions (exchanges). Even these restrictions never was included as formal regulations, they are gradually accepted as systematic restrictions. (Douglass, 2008)
  Or, to be precise, when informal institutional factors initiated from social life are accepted and recognized by state organs and promoted by state power, the informal system in the public law area can exist. For example, the informal system of civil servants enrollment refers to “a series of factors such as the value and belief of the official examination formed on a long-term basis, ethical norms, ethical principles, and ideologies.” (Wang & Gong, 2008) This system mainly forms during historical accumulation and social convention and thus accepted and recognized by state power. In practice, no matter formal or informal institutional discriminations, is very typical. As for the former one, for example, Article 8 of the Marriage Law in People’s Republic of China states:   Both the man and the woman desiring to contract a marriage shall register in person with the marriage registration office. If the proposed marriage is found to conform with the provisions of this Law, the couple shall be allowed to register and issued marriage certificates. The husband-and-wife relationship shall be established as soon as they obtain the marriage certificates. A couple shall go through marriage registration if it has not done so.
  This Article has limited marriage between only two different sexes and thus excludes the establishment of marriage of the same sex which apparently has become a formal institutional discrimination for the equal rights of marriage to the same-sex. And for the latter one, for example, the discrimination upon woman in China’s public servant examination is a typical informal institutional discrimination. Although the Constitution, the Labor Law, the Employment Promotion Act, and the Civil Servant Law and other laws clearly state that female and male enjoy equal employment rights, in the practice of recruiting civil servants, the discrimination against women has become very common no matter in the central government or in local governments. It is definitely institutional discrimination in informal system arrangements.
  3. FAULT AND NON-FAULT COEXIST
  For the subjective state of liability, tort liability law has changed from pure subjective fault to the coexistence of fault and non-fault. Ricoeur has pointed out:
  Contemporary history which is called as Liability Law prefers to give non-fault liability application scope under the pressure of related, safety, risk and such concepts from the technical layer of this term. However, non-fault liability has the tendency of replacing faulty concept, just as the anti-punishment of civil liability has to contain complete anti-self-accusation. (Ricoeur, 2007, p.28)
  Although Ricoeur’s analysis strengthened the importance of non-fault liability in modern liability law, he obviously overstated the wide application of non-fault principle. The reason that non-fault principle comes into being is nothing but because
  people want to see that when there is a lack of fault actions the compensation can be also made sure. Thus, the objective evaluation of damages has the trend of eliminating the subjective connection between actions and the doer. Just from this, the concept of non-fault liability forms. (Ricoeur, 2007, p.29)
  However, the coexistence of fault and non-fault liability indeed enriches the content of liability law and better protects citizens’ legal rights. The change of subjective constitutive elements of liability in Tort Liability Law also deeply affects the anti-discrimination law. Professor Li, Weiwei concludes:   The expansion of the scope of anti-discrimination law from direct discrimination to indirect discrimination can be considered as derived from the development of fault theory of tort law. This development has close relation with the people’s interests that anti-discrimination law protects. (Li, 2012)
  Professor Li, Weiwei thinks as intentional discrimination, direct discrimination obviously should have fault on its constitutive elements; while as neutral discrimination, indirect discrimination is not formed by having subjective intentions, instead, it is defined by the harmful consequences of the act, therefore, it should focus on the non-fault concept in subjective elements. This paper thinks that the conclusion of Professor Li, Weiwei also applies on institutional discrimination. In the institutional discrimination, indirect discrimination and direct discrimination also exist. For example, the “On further strengthening the recognition of urban residents entitled to basic living allowances” issued by the Ministry of Civil Affairs in 2010, when affirming the low income people, there is provisions on the type and condition of family property and family income. It is thought that family property refers to “securities, deposit, real estate, vehicles and other properties owned by family members who live together.” And family income is “the disposable income including income from wage and salary after tax and social security payment, business net income, income from property, and transferred income owned by all family members living together within a specified time limit.” From the literal aspect we can see that these provisions do not contain discrimination, however, if we refer to Article 3 of Marriage Law, it is not difficult to find out that the family relations recognized by Chinese laws only include spousal relationship, parent-child relationship, grandparent and grandchild relationship, sisterhood or brotherhood relationship, and other relationship based on heterosexual marriage. Homosexual marriage based relationships cannot be counted as family relations. We cannot say that the provisions of the Ministry of Civil Affairs intentionally discriminate homosexual persons, but the fact of the provisions indeed show that homosexual persons are excluded which is obviously an indirect discrimination. However, Article 3 of the Marriage Law is worth considering. As an expression of sexual freedom, homosexuality cannot be accused. However, due to the discrimination of religious culture, traditional morality, and the concept of child-bearing, homosexual persons are widely discriminated in social life. Legislators have accepted such social concepts and thus institutionalize and legalize such concepts by legislation. Therefore, the definition of family relations in Article 3 of Marriage Law is definitely direct discrimination for homosexual persons.   There is another subjective state of institutional discrimination worth study. There is legitimate institutional discrimination in history, or to say, the institutional discrimination in good faith. Then how should we define the subjective state of such institutional discrimination? This paper thinks that the historical legitimacy of institutional discrimination or the good will of the purpose of such design is relative. When the foundation of such legitimacy or good will does not exist or changes, if the public power refuses to amend, then the subjective state should be faulted. For example, the discrimination against women is not a real discrimination in history for a very long period and even be recognized as a kind of protection for women. With this concept in heart, the institution design of women’s discrimination usually shows man’s care and concern for them. “Men probably treat women as parents. … in another way, the care women’s life got is more than men.” (Brest, Levinson, Balkin, & Amar, 2002) The care-based institution design even affects women themselves. “Most women resign to fate and do not want to make any actions; … when they entered into the world, they take men’s opinions to bring into correspondence with men.” (Simone, 2011) Under such background, the discriminative arrangement in the system against women does not appear so dazzling but with some kind of reasonability. Such reasonability even lasts until recent era.
  The modern citizen Constitution also includes the modern constitutionalism. There is no clear prohibition on the discrimination on gender. It’s a reflection of the discrimination raised by real sex in politics and society. Therefore, in modern times, women are discriminated by many areas. (Sugihara, 2000)
  However, the historical legitimacy does not mean the institutional discrimination against women is legal at present. On the contrary, if there is still discriminative arrangement against women in institutional design, then the public power must have fault in subjective state.
  CONCLUSION
  As discussed above, the legal liability of institutional discrimination is an independent legal responsibility made up by subject of liability, way of acting, and subjective state. The reason that we study the constitution of institutional discrimination’s legal liability, on one hand, is to further discuss and investigate the content of the legal liability of institutional discrimination; on the other hand, the most significant meaning is to get rid of the limitation of formal legitimacy of analytical-positivist jurisprudence and to ascertain the legal liability of public power subjects’ institutional discriminations through the study of the constitution of legal liability of institutional discrimination. This is the premise of regulating institutional discrimination.   REFERENCES
  Brest, P., Levinson, S., Balkin, J. M., & Amar, A. (2002). Processes of constitutional decision making: Cases and materials (Vol. 2, pp.980-981). In F. J. Lu, Q. F. Zhou, Q. F. Zhang, & G. M. Shen (Trans.). Beijing: China University of Political Science and Law Press.
  Cane, P. (2008). Responsibility in law and morality (p.377). In L. H. Luo (Trans.). Beijing: The Commercial Press.
  Douglass, C. N. (2008). Institutions, institutional change and economic performance (Hang, Hang & Wei, Sen, trans., p.56). Shanghai: Truth and Wisdom Press; Shanghai Joint Publishing Press; Shanghai Peoples Publishing House.
  Li, H. P. (2012, November 24). Non-state public power: Basic categories of China’s constitutional jurisprudence (p.38). Proceedings of the 8th Academic Seminar of China Constitutional Law Basic Categories and Methodologies, Changchun.
  Li, W. W. (2012). Theory of anti-discrimination law (p.171). Beijing: Law Press China.
  Ren, X. R. (2007). Institutional discrimination and the function of equal rights protection institution – From the view of farmer rights protection. Contemporary Law Review, (2), 6.
  Ricoeur, P. (2007). The just (p.28). In C. M. Cheng (Trans.). Beijing: Law Press China.
  Si, H. W. (2011). System rationality and social order (p.127). Beijing, China: Intellectual Property Publishing House.
  Simone, de B. (2011). The second sex (p.187). In K. L. Zhang (Trans.). China: Shanghai Translation Publishing House.
  Sugihara, Y. (2000). The history of the constitution – New theory of comparative constitution (Lü, Chang, & Qu, Tao, trans., pp.120-121). Beijing, China: Social Sciences Academic Press.
  Wang, Q. M., & Gong, L. B. (2008). Conflict and convergence of China’s formal and informal institutions of civil servants employment. Public Administration, (5), 17.
  Wang, T. (2005). Analysis of formal and informal regulations of power rent-seeking. Journal of Shanxi University of Finance and Economics, 6, 3.
  Xin, M. (2005). On institution (p.102). Beijing: People’s Publishing House.
  Yao, G. J. (2006). Unconstitutional responsibility theory (p.163). Beijing: Intellectual Property Publishing House.
  Zhang, Q. F. (2004). Western constitutional government systems: United States constitution (Vol. 1, p.396). Beijing: China University of Political Science and Law Press.
其他文献
[摘 要]近年来,财务舞弊案件逐年增长,单单依靠事后中国证券监督管理委员会的警告和行政处罚已经难以满足市场经济正常发展的需要。审计报告作为利益关系人进行决策的重要工具得到了国内外的普遍认同,会计鉴定人员可以有效利用审计报告建立财务舞弊的事前预警机制。因此,文章以近四年来中国注册会计师协会披露的上市公司的审计报告为基础,对非标准审计报告的影响因素进行定量分析,同时深入研究审计报告和潜在财务舞弊事件之
期刊
[摘 要]随着社会经济的发展,商品房价格逐渐上涨,越来越多的人开始把目光投向二手房。二手房买卖中存在着交易不规范等问题,其中的法律风险不容忽视。文章就二手房交易过程中可能出现的法律风险,进行剖析和研究,提出切实可行的方法来预防法律风险。  [关键词]二手房;法律风险;预防  一、二手房交易的相关背景  二手房是指己经在房地产交易中心备过案、完成初始登记和总登记的、再次上市进行交易的房产。经过一手买
期刊
[摘 要]随着现代社会的发展和住房制度的改革,以按揭方式购买商品房已经成为我国城镇居民普遍采用的一种购房形式。目前部分城市房价上涨较快,房屋资源分配管理不够合理。新国五条的出台对按揭住房也产生了比较重大的影响。文章旨在通过实际调查与我国商品房预售的实践理论分析相结合,对按揭住房现实的法律问题的处理作一些分析探讨。  [关键词]个人按揭;住房;概况  [调查背景]为了实现购房安家的梦想,面对动辄百万
期刊
[摘 要]反映各时代社会生产、市民生活的代表性实物——老字号,是中国传统商业文化的象征,是民族风情的载体,是珍贵的文化遗产。随着经济的不断发展,市场竞争日趋激烈,中华老字号面临着前所未有的机遇和挑战。老字号在国外被抢注问题严峻,其面临生存危机和发展困境。因此,加强老字号的保护与发展意义重大,刻不容缓。但我国对于老字号的保护不尽如人意,不少老字号正在逐渐消失,如何完善对其的保护就显得十分重要了。文章
期刊
[摘 要]文章以民营银行的代表民生银行为例,运用罗伯特·C·希金斯的可持续增长模型对我国民营银行的可持续增长进行实证研究。研究发现,样本银行的实际增长率高于同期可持续增长率,继续进一步分析提出了加快流程银行建设、发展零售业务和中间业务、发挥整体经营协同效应、转变融资模式、加强内部控制与风险管理等建议。  [关键词]民营银行;可持续增长;民生银行  引言  2012年5月,中国银监会发布发《关于鼓励
期刊
[摘 要]日趋严峻的大学生就业形势已经成为国内亟需解决的问题。随着网络经济的日益发展,大学生网络创业逐渐成为解决大学生就业问题的一种方式,对促进以创业带动就业具有重要意义。笔者在充分调研的基础之上,总结出大学生网络创业的现状,并制定适当的网络创业引导策略,为大学生自主创业和高等学校创业教育提供有针对性的决策参考。  [关键词]大学生;网络创业;创业前景;保障措施  大学生网络创业不是偶然,而是经济
期刊
[摘 要]检察机关作为国家的法律监督机关,公正文明执法是社会公众对司法信任和服从的基础。积极利用互联网与人民群众互动交流,为人民群众服务,接受人民群众监督,对提升检察机关的公信力有着十分重要的作用。但是,在实践中尚有许多问题需要解决。笔者尝试从互联网的利用与舆情管理的角度来提出在互联网时代提升检察机关公信力的可行之路。  [关键词]网络时代;检察机关公信力;互联网运用;舆情管理  司法具有高度的公
期刊
[摘 要]社会主义市场经济的建立和完善,使我国行政管理的客观环境发生了变化。文章通过介绍权变理论的起源,概述了权变理论的卓越贡献,结合我国领导方式存在的问题,对变革行政领导方式提出了几点建议。  [关键词]权变理论;领导方式;变革;行为  权变理论认为,不存在一种固定不变、普遍适用的领导理论与领导行为方式,领导者的有效性有赖于领导者、被领导者和环境这三个因素的交互关系而定。在我国的行政领导实践中,
期刊
怎么是你一个人出来?没有人迎接吗?
期刊
图1-3是我们常见的马的形象。漫画的拟人画法就是把动物或物体按人的喜怒哀乐、行为举止去画,可以画读书、看报、吹打弹拉的,但要尽最符合你要画的动物或物体的特点,把不可能变为可能,如图4-13。你还可以画出更多拟人画法的马,希望全国的小朋友们也可以把你用拟人画法画的动物或物体寄给我们,我们会在漫画课堂栏目中选登发表的。
期刊